Friday, January 24, 2014

Methodological Dualism

One of the biggest problems I have in my thinking is the methodological dualism that I've inherited from Collingwood. I was reading about how German philosophers and sociologists in the 19th and early 20th century made a distinction between the way we explain humans and the way we explain nature. Collingwood took this distinction very seriously and famously argued that humans can only be understood in terms of thought, whereas nature can be handled in terms of laws.

One of the central things driving this kind of methodological divide is that of regularity and by extension prediction.

Gotta go!

Wednesday, January 22, 2014

An Aborted, or Temporarily Halted, Essay

I began this essay but never pursued it. It was tentatively titled: 'Knowing Mind, Scientifically and Historically'. It was going to be an exploration of Collingwood's claim that philosophy of mind can be fully dissolved into history due to the fact that mind is only what mind does. Mind defined as pure activity needs to be studied only in concrete instances, that is, through history. Mind therefore cannot be studied by the natural sciences, which deal with regularity and generality.

As I move through my numbered days I continue to ask: Who am I? Or, even more urgently, I ask: What am I? This world remains a mystery to me. My place in it is still opaque, rarely presenting open fields, never pulling me into a full, comforting embrace. I’ve yet to hear the voice, which some seem to hear, calling: ‘You are perfect. You belong here. I love you.’ I merely move forward, timidly groping in the dark, stillness being foreign to my nature.

There are other voices, though. No shortage of them, in fact. Everywhere I turn there is a competing vision of what I am or what I can become: A Man. A Lover. A Husband. A Father. A Sane Person. A Healthy Person. A Law Abiding Citizen. A Sexual Being. A Soul. An Ego. An Id. Lastly, and most unequivocally, A Brain. 

I can’t deny that I am, or may become, many of those things. Yet none of them feels quite right. None of those words will ever capture me. The question, ‘What am I?’ retains its weight, and I still carry it. 
Self-knowledge is by necessity incomplete. We humans are the object that does not stay still, as they say. Or, more precisely, we are the animals that change in response to the way we speak of ourselves, we create ourselves by telling stories about ourselves. The quest for self-knowledge is thus reflexive: it continually turns in on itself, endlessly reacts to itself, and ideally becomes a kind of narrative self-creation

I’m here to spend some time reflecting on this question, What am I? What does it mean to know myself? I’ll be doing some reflecting on my own thoughts and experiences, but I also have some philosophical claims I’d like to develop. Chiefly, the idea that contemporary philosophy of mind, with its emphasis on cognitive and neuroscience, is not producing something we can call ‘knowledge of mind.’ It answers not the question ‘what is the mind?’, but ‘what makes the mind possible?’. This question about the mind’s conditions of possibility, moreover, is always asked in the spirit of natural science: with the desire to produce an account of the mind that is consistent with and utilizes the insights of physics, chemistry, and biology. Such a union to the natural sciences, however, is precisely what prevents philosophy of mind from answering the question ‘what is the mind?’ For embracing the natural sciences as the path to self-knowledge means importing an assumption that is detrimental to the study of one’s own mind: that all explanations must be given in terms of regularities, generalities, and abstractions. 

Knowledge of one’s own mind can never be a generic knowledge, applicable to all people in all times and places. No, it must be a unique knowledge of my particular mind in its own unique time and place. The only mind accessible to us is our own, therefore anyone who claims to know mind can only be claiming to know their own mind. This claim holds two interrelated implications for philosophy of mind. First, it means there can be no set of theoretical propositions that can hand knowledge of mind to us ready-made, we must delve into ourselves, plunge into the depths of our own minds and learn first hand who we are and what minds are. In short, there is no substitute for genuine reflection on ourselves. Second, this implies that any theoretical proposition made by philosophy of mind must be subservient to this process of personal reflection. What philosophy of mind tells us about what makes the mind possible is therefore not knowledge of mind in itself, but a set of propositions that can foster productive reflection on our own minds. I am proposing that we regard philosophy of mind in precisely the way that Shunryu Suzuki regards Buddhism: 

The purpose of studying Buddhism is not to study Buddhism, but to study ourselves. It is impossible to study ourselves without some teaching. If you want to know what water is you need science, and the scientist needs a laboratory. In the laboratory there are various ways in which to study what water is. Thus it is possible to know what kind of elements water has, the various forms it takes, and its nature. But it is impossible thereby to know water in itself. It is the same thing with us. We need some teaching, but just by studying the teaching alone, it is impossible to know what ‘I’ in myself am. Through the teaching we may understand our human nature. But the teaching is not we ourselves; it is some explanation of ourselves. So if you are attached to the teaching, or to the teacher, that is a big mistake. The moment you meet a teacher, you should leave the teacher, and you should be independent


In claiming that philosophy of mind is subservient to reflection I am casting my allegiance to a school of philosophy advocated by Michel Foucault. In The Government of Self and Others Foucault argues that modern philosophy takes two dominant forms. The first is committed to the “question of the conditions of possibility of a true knowledge.... the analytic of truth” (20). This approach is typical for American philosophy of mind, with its emphasis on what makes the mind possible based on what we know about the natural world. This kind of philosophy strives more often for a normative scientific theory: A set of general propositions meant to identify and explain the regularities of a phenomenon, typically with the goal of prediction and manipulation. Alternatively, philosophy can strive to answer the question “What is present reality? what is the present field of our experiences?” (20). This is Foucault’s project, a type of philosophical reflection that strives not for complete systems, but for practical insights into ourselves and the world. A philosophy of mind carried out in this way would regard general propositions about the mind as incomplete in themselves, and would rather regard them as aids to thinking about ourselves in the present. Philosophy of mind, in other words, is not knowledge of mind at all, but a tool that allows us to know the only mind we can know, our own. 

My God.

I want to begin blogging with greater regularity. My graduate school applications are out and I'm (im)patiently waiting for decisions.

This blog has been an interesting and rewarding part of my life. It was about a year ago that I stopped writing regularly on it. My output was quite extensive for a while. Then I slowed down. I wanted to focus on applications, I began to doubt the seriousness of my thinking.

I feared that I would never go to school, that I was just some self-centered young man who liked to spin his pseudo-philosophical wheels.

Now that my applications are in I can rest a little bit more easily. I've taken the first step in becoming an academic, or a teacher, or some kind of professional thinker. I remain just some guy for the time being.

One of the strangest parts of the application process was dealing with the homelessness that I feel in the world. I don't know what it means to belong. I suppose I belong in my family, and I suppose I belong among some of my friends. But somehow I just always have this feeling of not belonging.

I once wrote a poem about how

I am not a stranger

How this is not a strange land.

Yet, I don't believe myself. I don't dwell very comfortably. I take great pleasure in feeling that feeling with clarity, though.

In applying to schools I certainly had this idea, this vague, barely conscious hope, that I would find a home in a university: that a group of people would greet me in a way I felt true to my heart.

This homelessness confounds me. I think I partly inherited it from my father. He partly inherited it from Nietzsche. I partly inherited it from Nietzsche.

I recently read Twilight of the Idols while my friend Jeremy was in town. Nietzsche is his major influence. One night we drank quite a lot of wine and were getting into the thick of talking about Nietzsche. My emotional response surprised me.

Even though I was the one doing most of the talking, I was experiencing the conversation more as a listener than a speaker. I had had enough to drink that words were flowing from me without hesitation.

I told Jeremy that I felt like I was reliving the trauma of Nietzsche: the trauma he felt in his own life, the trauma that he unleashed upon the world, the trauma of a world without meaning, the trauma of being responsible for creating my own values (not that I buy into the idea of value creation, anyways).

He is a serious challenge, one that I'm excited to be taking on.

I'll be posting here more regularly.

Tuesday, January 21, 2014

Composure, External and Internal

Sometimes I tell my friends that I am losing my mind.

Sometimes they tell me that I seemed fine, that externally I seemed normal.

Sometimes I don't change my behavior, but my thoughts run wild.

I don't know what it is that changes.

I am able to act in one way, but my mind is going another way.

Is my mind just a way of acting?

Saturday, January 18, 2014

Collingwood, Strauss, and Two Kinds of Historicism

I've recently become aware of Leo Strauss's criticisms of Collingwood. Strauss claimed that the two greatest threats to modern political philosophy (epitomized by Socrates) were positivism and historicism. Collingwood, he apparently claimed, was the most sophisticated proponent of historicism. Some of Strauss's claims, however, don't square with my understanding of Collingwood.

Both of these men deserve my consideration, and I intend to give both of them plenty more of my time. Here, however, I want to offer a few preliminary thoughts on what I see as shortcomings in Strauss's views on Collingwood.

All I've read of Strauss's criticism so far came from his review of The Idea of History, a book that cannot be considered as representative of Collingwood's thought. Tricky tricky, that book.

I can't write patiently now.

Strauss mainly focuses on the idea that Collingwood is a historicist.

He mainly seems to detest the deterministic nature of Collingwood's determinism.

Collingwood speaks of necessity. Not of determinism.

Collingwood, I think, is not a historicist in a determinist sense. The first sense.

Collingwood is a historicist in the sense of being a contextualist. He always pays attention to the historical setting in which a thought was taking place, emphasizing that we should try to think just like the author thought.

Strauss harps on Collingwood for not properly reenacting Greek thought.

He never says that the idea of reenactment is flawed in itself, only that Collingwood failed to do it properly.

Strauss's student, Allan Bloom, moreover, often uses metaphors that invoke Collingwood's notion of reenactment.

I think that distinguishing these kinds of historicism can do some help in reconciling my allegiance to Collingwood with my fondness for Allan Bloom and my budding interest in Strauss.

This is not clear. I want to write more on this soon.

I also want to write on Collingwood's anti-positivistic tendencies, his insistence on the unpredictability of the world, and his idea of reenactment as a way of learning about the human world. Sounds a lot like Clausewitz, Taleb, and nonlinearity stuff.